e-LV (Archives Numériques de l’École de Lvov et de Varsovie/ Cyfrowe Archiwum Kazimierza Twardowskiego/ Kazimierz Twardowski Digital Archives) est un projet au sein des Archives Poincaré, Laboratoire d’Histoire des Sciences et de Philosophie (UMR 7117), CNRS/Université de Lorraine. Les e-ARCHIVES du site elv-akt.net contiennent une bibliothèque numérique des manuscrits et des œuvres de Twardowski et des philosophes de son entourage, ainsi que les divers documents (textes, photo, enregistrements vidéo et phono) les concernant. Les ÉDITIONS e-LV visent l’édition critique et la traduction des manuscrits archivés en mode texte. Elles se conforment en ce sens aux normes éditoriales et techniques en vigueur (XML/TEI). En tant qu’infrastructure internationale de RECHERCHES les Archives e-LV ont pour but de promouvoir les recherches, les mémoires et les publications relatives à la philosophie analytique polonaise. Nous présentons aussi l’ACTUALITÉ du projet.

Choix de la langue

Archives Elv-Akt

Pour consulter en exclusivité les Archives e-LV et recevoir les actualités, devenez membre

Comment nous citer ?

Sur la fiche de chaque archive électronique, vous trouverez une référence bibliographique à la norme française afin de vous permettre de citer convenablement le document.

Recherche

Recherche avancée

Colloques

<span style="font-weight: bold; "><EM>Encodage de "Genesis and history of Twardowski’s theory of actions and products: From the psychology of consciousness to the general theory of action "</EM></span> (PROJETS E-LV - Nicole Dufournaud)

Encodage de "Genesis and history of Twardowski’s theory of actions and products: From the psychology of consciousness to the general theory of action "

Si vous utilisez ce document pour la recherche, prière de référencer l'URL du document.
If you use this document for research, please reference this URL.
Contrat Creative Commons 'Paternité - Pas d'utilisation commerciale - Pas de modification'
Cette création est mise à disposition sous un contrat Creative Commons "Paternité - Pas d'utilisation commerciale - Pas de modification" .
This work is licensed under a Creative Commons "Attribution-Noncommercial-No Derivative Works" 2.0 France License .

Jerzy Bobryk
Genesis and history of Twardowski’s theory of actions and products:
From the psychology of consciousness to the general theory of action
Introduction


Kazimierz Twardowski was born in 1866 in Vienna, where he later studied
under Franz Brentano. He joined the circle of Brentano’s followers which included E.
Husserl,A.Meinong, K. Stumpf, and others. In 1892 he visited Wund’s psychological
laboratory and studied shortly under Karl Stumpf. In 1894, his work Zur Lehre vom
Inhalt und Gegenstand der Vorstellungen (On the content and object of presentation)
presented as a thesis qualified him as assistant professor (habilitation). After his
habilitation he moved (in 1895) to Lvov, where he held a professorship for 35 years at
the Jan Kazimierz University. Twardowski died in 1938.


In philosophy, Twardowski initiated the Lvov-Warsaw school, which is
sometimes termed the Polish analytical philosophy. Twardowski concentrated mainly
on building in Poland a real scientific philosophy; he also founded the first Polish
laboratory of experimental psychology. He was the master of famous Polish
philosophers, logicians, sociologists and psychologist, like Władysław Tatarkiewicz,
Tadeusz Kotarbiński, Kazimierz Ajdukiewicz, Innocenty Bocheński, Alfred Tarski, Jan
Łukasiewicz, Stanisław Leśniewski, Stanisław Ossowski, Maria Ossowska,
Władysław Witwicki, and others.


Twardowski wrote in German and in Polish, his works dealt with the analysis of
philosophical, psychological, logical and ethical concepts.


It is not an easy task to give a brief summary of Twardowski’s intellectual
development. His starting point was Brentano’s theory of intentional acts, but finally
he reverted to the analytical method of the positivist tradition, although he never
postponed basic assumptions of Brentano’s philosophical psychology. In other
words, Twardowski’s philosophy was an original synthesis of phenomenology and
linguistic philosophy. It is worth mentioning that he made this synthesis at the
beginning of 20th century, several decades before the appearance of British linguistic philosophy.


I would like to present here only one aspect of development of Twardowski’s
thought: his concept of intentional act and relationship between the human
consciousness and the human action.


The following figure is an ideogram of relationships between Twardowski’s
philosophy and psychology, phenomenological philosophy and linguistic philosophy

Figure one: Theory of intentionality and its developement
Brentano’s theory of intentional acts


Franz Brentano in his Psychologie vom empirischen Standpunkt argued
that mental phenomena have unique property: they are intentional. Our mental states are
in some sense directed at objects and states of affairs in the world. If someone has a
belief it is a belief that something is the case. If I have a wish it must be a wish to do
something. If Mary or John have an image it must be an imagination of something.
Our mental states could be directed at material or ideal or fictional objects. I can
believe that the King of France is a good-looking man even if there is no King of
France. I can imagine Pegasus, I can think about fictitious numbers. In all the cases
there is something which is called the object of my consciousness. In other words,
every mental phenomenon is characterized by its intentional object. The intentional
object of my act of perception is the perceived material object. The intentional object
of my act imagination of Pegasus is the fictional mythological Pegasus. The Pegasus
could be an object of my thinking or believing. I can believe that Pegasus exists. This
directness or “aboutness” is the first property of intentional acts.


The second property of intentional acts is something, which can be called
self-determination or teleological determination. The course or development of my act
of imagination of Pegasus depends on my will and my intention (in this case it is the
intention of an imagination of Pegasus). It seems the goal or the target of my act
determines the course of this act. The factual or apparent feature of any mental act is
its teleological determination.

Twardowski (1894/1977) on the content and object of presentation


We can assume that Pegasus is a creature that exist in external world, for example, a
result of genetic engineering. This physically existing Pegasus could be an object of
my visual perception. The mental action of perception produces – in some sense –
the mental representation of Pegasus. This product of the action of perception exists
as long as the action of perception lasts. But if Pegasus is a material creature, the
duration of its existence is longer than the visual perception of Pegasus. Another
mental action, the action of imagination or the action of remembering can produce an
imagined or remembered Pegasus. The imagined Pegasus can exist even if the
material Pegasus does not exist.

It seems that in the case mentioned above there are two different objects: material
Pegasus and its mental representation. In his Zur Lehre vom Inhalt und Gegenstand
der Vorstellungen
Kazimierz Twardowski argued that his master Franz Brentano
used the word “object” in two senses: on the one hand, for independently existing
entity to which our mental actions are directed, as it were; and, on the other, for the
mental product, picture, representation and presentation of a real entity. The former is
termed the transcendent object of mental action, the latter the content or the
immanent object of this action.


The immanent object or the content of mental action is a mental or psychological
entity, and it is a result of mental processes of a particular subject (person).
The transcendent object of mental action is mostly a material or physical entity and it
is independent on my mentality. If I am thinking about ideal objects like triangles or
numbers they have objective properties. Any triangle has three straight sides and
three angles even if I do not know about that. Ideal or abstract object are also
independent of my mind. However I can have mental representation of these objects.

Acts of consciousness and psychophysical actions


The difference between “content” and “object” of my (or your) action of
imagining the Eiffel Tower is analogous to the difference between a camera picture of
the tower and the tower itself.


When a photographer is taking a photo of the tower, a photograph results. When I
am imagining, or remembering the tower, mental picture of it comes into existence.
When I am speaking about the Eiffel Tower, it is the content of my mental act and my
speech act. “The content” is a product of my mental act like a photo is a product of
the work of a camera. The product of a camera work is a representation of a material
object like the content of a mental act may be a representation of a particular material
object. We can imagine a non-existing (fictional) object, as well as we can produce a
representation of non-existing object using an electronic camera and a computer. action or act content of product object imaginining the perception the object of perception speaking the content the reference painting the portrait the model



The theory of actions and products
Actions and products



In such pairs as:
to race – the race,
to cry – the cry,
to think – the thought,
to speak – the speech,
to jump – the jump,
to walk – the walk,
to inform – the denunciation,
the first word denotes an action, the second the product of this action.
The difference between the two words is not only of grammar but also of meaning as
the two words have different denotation (Twardowski 1912/1979). When we argue, a
discussion results, when we think a thoughts result, when we construct a
construction results. W may say that a jump is a product of jumping and a song is a
product of singing. Various kinds of actions and products can be reduced to two
basic kinds, that is, physical actions and products, and mental actions and products.
The former category covers: “to jump – the jump”, “to swim – the swimming”, the
latter: “to think – the thought”, “to expect – the expectation”. Moreover, from among
physical actions and products we should separate out those that are psychophysical,
namely, those in which a physical action is accompanied by a mental one, which
somehow affects that physical action and, accordingly, its product. This applies to
actions and products such as: “to lie – the lie”, “to cry – the cry”, “to speak – the
speech”, “to write – the writing”, “to paint – the painting” (Twardowski 1912/1979).

Durable products and non-durable products


Relations between actions and products are clear and simple from the logical
and grammatical point of view, however, these relations are more complicated from
ontological and empirical point of view (Twardowski 1912/1979). There is a gradation
from cases in which a product almost merges with the action of which it is the result
to cases in which a product is clearly distinct from the action. We can predicate many
things about products that we do not predicate about actions (Twardowski
1912/1979). We may say that the certain questions are incomprehensible or unclear,
which is not to say that posing questions is an incomprehensible or vague action. In
many cases the distinction between an action and its product must be substantiated,
but here are other cases where that distinction is self-evident. The first kind of
products might be termed non-durable, those product which exists only as long as
the action that produces them lasts. A speech exists as long as the action of
speaking continues, a thought, as long as someone is thinking. Anyway, it is often
said that the ideas or thoughts of a thinker outlive him, but in this case we do not
mean the continuing existence of the thought, an existence independent of any
action. We denote the repetition of actions and products: from generation to
generation similar actions and products are repeated. By way of analogy, we may
say that ideas, expectations, desires are inherent in that sense that they exist in our
mind, even though in a given moment we are not performing an appropriate action
that produce these ideas or desires. But as a matter of fact we simply mean that we
have certain psychological disposition (in the next chapter we will discuss the nature
of this disposition), which may make us produce in the future the same products we
produce in the past. Hence we may speak of continuing existence of products of this
kind, meaning either repetition of the same actions and products, or their potential
existence. The product may be termed non-durable in the virtue of their not actually
existing longer than the actions that produce them.


There are, however, products that can last longer than the action which
produces them. Examples of such actions and products comprise: “to draw – the
drawing”, “to write – the writing”, “to type – the typescript”, “to program the computer
– the written computer program”. We employ etymological figures and speak of
“building buildings”, “painting paintings”, and „drawing – drawings”. Products of this
kind may be termed durable products (Twardowski 1912/1979). Certain products may
continue to exist after the action from which they result ended, because these actions
transformed, or affected, something that had existed before the particular action
began and continued to exist after termination of that action. This “something” can be
called the material of the action. The action itself from which durable products result
consists in modifying the material; the action changes the configuration of its particles
or changes it in some other way. The product of that action is merely a new
configuration, modification or transformation of the material since that material
existed prior to the action. Thus in calling a drawing the product of the action of drawing, we do not mean that the particles of graphite and the paper are products of
the action of drawing, since the product is only a given configuration of particles of
graphite on paper.


Amongst actions and products we may single out those that are
psychophysical, namely those in which a physical action is accompanied by a mental
action which somehow affects that physical action and, consequently, its product. A
product obtained in this way is termed a psychophysical product (Twardowski
1912/1979). The text written on the paper is usually a product of a human mental and
physical actions, and therefore it may be termed the psychophysical product. We
may say that the human culture and civilization is a collection of psychophysical
products. Some of them – like books or paintings – are durable products, others –
like musical performances – are non-durable.

There are three categories of actions and products: physical actions and
products, mental or psychological actions and products, and psychophysical actions
and products. actions and products non - durable durable physical to dance (and) the dance
to walk (and) the walk to build (and) the building
to cook (and) the food mental to think (and) the thought
to perceive (and) the perception psycho-physical to speak (and) the speach
to inform (and) the information to paint (and) the painting
to write (and) the text
Fig.3 Actions and products

Mental products and non-durable products


Kazimierz Twardowski (1912/1979) argues that any mental product is not
durable in itself; it exists only as long as the mental action which produces it. A
thought exists as long as someone is thinking, a mental representation of the
perceived object exist in my mind as long as I am perceiving it. Of course, after
perception I may initiate a mental action of imagining or remembering
of previously perceived object which produce a new product, another psychological representation
of previously perceived thing. Products of psychological processes of thinking are
not permanent and they tend to disappear when the process comes to an end.
Human conviction of their durability comes from our habit to produce and employ
psychophysical products such as written text, picture, logical notation, etc., i.e. the
ways of bringing permanence to the fleeting products of human thinking. In other
words, mental products are not durable, but because of physical actions that usually
accompany particular mental actions there are durable psychophysical products as
writings, drawings or simply graphic signs. At the moment when a psychophysical
actions occurs, both the mental product and the psychophysical product exist
simultaneously (Twardowski 1912/1979). We may say that the majority of human
actions are, as a matter of fact, psychophysical actions.


Twardowski’s thesis on the non-durability of mental products is a controversial
part of his theory. However it is worth to say that Urlic Neisser (a prominent cognitive
psychologist) presented – independently and 50 years after Twardowski – a very
similar conception of mental acts (mental processes in his language). According to
Neisser (1967) the traditional theories of human cognitive processes are based on
the assumption of durability of mental representations. This approach Neisser termed
“the reappearance hypothesis”, which, in his opinion, had originated from the English
empiricist philosophers. Classical psychology assumed that several cognitive units,
like “ideas”, “concepts”, stored in human mind can be used several times. The same
“memory”, image, idea or other cognitive unit can disappear and reappear
over and over again (Neisser 1967, p. 281). In Twardowski’s terms this would be the
hypothesis of the permanence, durability and repeated manifestation in human
mental acts a fixed product of previous mental acts.


To this traditional reappearance hypothesis Neisser counterpoised his own,
based on the assumption of the impermanence of product of mental activity, i.e. the
utilization hypothesis. According to Neisser, concept ideas and other mental
representations are not fixed products separate and apart from the acts themselves
which, once created, continue to exist in a ready form and may be re-used many
times. Thus human mind stores not so much ready ideas, concepts and
representations, as traces of previous cognitive acts, which allow for a repetition of
the act itself and obtaining similar results of the repeated cognitive activity. „Recall,
by way of image, takes places when a new construction is largely under the control of
what remains from an earlier one. Recall in words, on the other hand is a new verbal
synthesis which may be based on information from a number of sources, including
not only traces of earlier verbalizations, but perhaps visual images an other
constructions as well.” (Neisser 1967, p. 285). Ulric Neisser claims that traces of
cognitive acts are not simply “revived” or “reactivated” in the act of recall; instead,
the stored fragments are used as information to support a new construction. “It is as if
the bone fragments used by the paleontologist did not appear in the model he builds
at all - as indeed they need not, is it is to represent a fully fleshed-out, skin-covered
dinosaur. The bones can be thought of, somewhat loosely, as remnants of structure
which created and supported the original dinosaur, and thus a sources of information
about how to reconstruct it.” (Neisser 1967, p. 286).

John Searle’s theory of human action


In 1984 John Searle presented his theory of human action, which is – like
Twardowski’s theory of action – based on the theory of intentionality. According to
the classical theory of intentionality (which in fact is the theory of human
consciousness), human mental processes are characteristic of two
features: the first feature of conscious psychological act is that all mental acts are intentional; they are
about “something”; the second, is that they are “personal”, “mono-subjective” or
“private”, which means that only the subject of mental acts has privileged and
immediate access to them. The other persons may have only indirect knowledge
about my mental processes and their content. They may learn about it from my
verbal expressions or deduce it from my behavior. This mediated and indirect
knowledge is deceptive and open to doubt. Only the subject of a mental act has
immediate and unquestionable knowledge about the content of his/her mental act. I
am aware of myself and my internal mental states and assume that they are distinct
from the selves and mental states of other people.


By way of analogy, in his description of the structure of human action John
Searle (1984, p. 58) emphasized that an important feature of human action is that a
person is in a special position to know what he/she is doing. The subject of any
action does not have to observe himself/herself or conduct an investigation to see
which action he/she is performing, or trying to perform. Because of that, we are able
to identify and explain quite effortlessly the our own behavior. “If I am going for a walk to
Hyde Park, there are any number of other things that are happened in the course
of my walk, but their descriptions do not describe my intentional action […] So, for
example I am also moving in the general direction to Patagonia, shaking the hair on
my head up an down, wearing out my shoes, and moving a lot of air molecules.
However, [...] if you say to me Are you trying to walk to Hyde Park or trying to get
closer to Patagonia?>> I have no hesitation in giving an answer even though the
physical movements that I made might be appropriate for either answer.” (Searle
1984, p. 58). In other words, we can say that any human action consist of its
“content” or “preferred description”, and that “content” or “preferred description” is
first and foremost known by the subject of action.


This “content” or “description” of a human action is a mental component (an
intentional component – in Searle’s words) of human action, which means that doing
something I am conscious, or potentially conscious, what I am doing, or at least,
going to do. These mental or intentional states sometimes cause things to happen:
“if I want to go to the movies, and I go to the movies, normally my desire will cause
the very event it represents, my going to the movies. In such cases there is internal
connection between the cause and the effect, […] the cause both represents and
brings about the effect” (Searle 1984, p. 61) John Searle calls such kind of cause and
effect relations “intentional causation”. Intentional causation means that the intention
of my action, in other words, mental component of my psychophysical action, is both
the cause of this action and the element of it.


There are two basic kinds of the intention of action: prior
intentions and intentions in action. Some actions are premeditated, they are results of some sort of
planning in advance, other actions are spontaneous, we do something without any
prior reflection. In the first case we have the prior
intention; in the second, is the intention in action or immanent intention. This is the intention we have while we
actually performing an action. “For example, in a normal conversation, one doesn’t
reflect on what one is going to say next, one just says it. In such cases, there is
indeed an intention, but it is not an intention formed prior to the performance of the action.” (Searle 1984, p. 65).
Searle’s thesis on the intentional causation of action is – in my opinion – a
hypothesis on the possibility of self-determination of human action. It seems the goal
or the target of my act determines (or may determine) the course of this act. The
factual or apparent feature for any human action is its teleological determination or
self-determination. We have said the same about the determination of act of consciousness.

Mental acts and brain processes


Investigating mental acts, or mental events, we have to face “the mind-body
problem”, which is the problem of explaining how human mental states and acts are
related to the states and processes in our brain. Can we assume that words “mind”
and “brain” are two names of one thing? If brain and mind are identical, why are we
speaking about “mental acts” not about “brain acts”? Why for thousands of years
have philosophers been trying to solve the problem of ontological and causal
relations between the human mind and the human brain, mental acts and brain
processes? Since the seventeenth century philosophers have been convinced that
mental phenomena are “subjective” whereas brain (i.e. physiological) processes are
”objective”. One can study human mind with the use of psychological (e.g.
introspective) methods whereas the brain can be researched with the use of objective
experimental methodology. Should we assume the non-identity of the mind and the
brain?


We may consider the mind-body problem investigating – on the one hand –
relationship between mind itself and mental functions, and – on the other hand –
relations between brain functions and mind acts.


The term “function” has two meanings. The first one is mathematical or quasi-
mathematical: when we say “X is a function of Y “, we mean that variable quantity of
X depends on variable quantity of Y. For example, it is said in physics that air-
pressure is a function of its temperature because the air-pressure must change when
the air temperature changes.


The second meaning of the term “function” refers to the special activity or
purpose of a person or thing. In this case we are saying that the function of the heart
is to pump blood through the body or that the function of the teacher is to teach students.


These two different ways of understanding the term “function” are applied in
the psychological and philosophical discourse. We may say that “the mind is a
function of the brain” (e.g. the mental process is a function of brain process) and
saying this we mean that the mental states and processes are changing due to the
changes of brain states and processes. It is the quasi-mathematical understanding of
the expression: “the mind is a function of the brain”. However, the same expression
may have another and entirely different sense; and saying: “the mind is a function of
the brain” we simply mean that the function of brain is to perform various mental acts
or processes, like to think, to feel, or to be aware of something.


According to Twardowski the phrase: “the mind is a function of the brain” may
be entirely and undoubtedly true if we understand it in a quasi-mathematical way: our
mental states have to change when our brain processes change. Using John Searle
(1984, p. 18) words we may say that: “Mental phenomena, all mental phenomena
whether conscious or unconscious, visual or auditory, pains, tickles, itches, thoughts,
indeed, all of our mental life, are caused by processes going on in the brain”.
However, according to Twardowski, the phrase “the mind is a function of the brain” is
not true, if we understand the word “function” as a synonym of “action” or “act”,
because it is uncertain that brain itself is able to perform all our mental acts. We
should rather say that all human mental acts (as well as the physical acts) are
performed by the whole person (Twardowski 1897/1965, p.95-96) . If human brain
was isolated from the rest of the body it wouldn’t perform any mental action.


In order to explain Twardowski’s idea I will put it in other words and another
context. Speaking about “the brain being isolated from the body” we may imagine
something like a science-fictional situation or a thought-experiment in which, as a
result of a surgical procedure, the brain has been removed from the body and placed
in a life-support system. I believe (and Twardowski would believe) that a brain
isolated from the rest of the body (e. g. from all visual or auditory receptors and
muscles) and placed in a life-support system could not perform normal psychological
functions. All normal psychological functions are performed by the whole person,
therefore the second meaning of the phrase “the mind is a function of the brain” is
false. If this phrase is not true we have to reject the identity of the mental acts and
the brain processes. In other words, the neurophysiological processes are performed
by the brain (or in the brain) whereas the whole person performs mental acts (e.g.
psychological functions).


On that point Twardowski and Searle have slightly different opinions.
Twardowski represents the traditional dualistic ontology while Searle’s point of view is
much more complicated. Searle’s solution of the mind-body problem is called “the
new dualism” or “the methodological dualism”. The methodological dualism is the
opinion that there are two different levels of the scientific description of the mind: the
psychological level and the nuerophysiological level. On the one hand, Searle (1984
p. 19) accepted the mind-brain ontological identity and claimed that: “Pains and other
mental phenomena just are features of the brain (and perhaps the rest of the central
nervous system)”. On the other hand, he added, (Searle 1984 p. 22) that we can not
say that: “This neuron is in pain, this neuron is experiencing thirst”. The mental terms
are useless on the neuropsychological level, as well as neurophysiological, biochemical and physical terminology is out of use on the mental level of scientific
description (e.g. in psychology) .

References

Neisser, Ulric (1967), Cognitive Psychology, Appleton-Century-Crofts , New York. Searle,
John R.(1984), Minds , Brains and Science, Harvard University Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts.
Twardowski, Kazimierz (1894/1977), On the content and object of presentation, Martinus Nijhoff ,The Hague.
Twardowski, Kazimierz (1912/1979), Actions and products. Comments on the border area of psychology, grammar and logic. In: Jerzy Pelc (ed), Semiotics in Poland 1894-1969, Reidel, Boston.
Twardowski, Kazimierz(1897/1965),Psychologia wobec fizjologii i filozofii (Psychology in the face of physiology and philosophy). In: Teresa Rzepa (ed), Psychologia w szkole lwowsko-warszawskiej (Psychology of the Lvov-Warsaw school) ,PWN, Warszawa.

Retour à l'accueil

Retour à la page précédente

Accueil | Inscription | CONTACTS | Conditions d'utilisation | Mentions légales | Espace membres | Espace privé
© ELV-AKT, 2007-2025.
Dernière mise à jour : Lundi 20 janvier 2025